Published in S. Krimsky & J. Gruber (Eds.), Genetic Explanations: Sense and Nonsense.  Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 2012.

 

 

 

The Fruitless Search for Genes in Psychiatry and Psychology: Time to Re-examine a Paradigm

 

 

Jay Joseph

 

 

Carl Ratner

Distinguished Visiting Professor of Psychology

Imam University

Riyadh, Saudi Arabia

www.sonic.net/~cr2

 

 

ABSTRACT

 

 

The past three decades have witnessed the failure of gene finding efforts in psychiatry and psychology. One rarely considered explanation for this failure is that the genes presumed to underlie psychiatric disorders and psychological traits do not exist. Recently, leading molecular genetic researchers have developed the "missing heritability" concept to explain these failures. Although the search for genes is based on the results of previous studies of families, twins, and adoptees, the authors argue that these studies are subject to environmental biases which may have confounded researchersÕ conclusions in favor of genetics. They conclude by calling on the scientific community to embark on a serious reassessment of the validity of family, twin, and adoption studies in light of the dramatic failures of gene finding efforts, and to consider non-reductionist culturally-oriented psychological theories that will lead to a more fruitful understanding of the origins of psychiatric disorders and psychological trait variation. 

 

 

 

 


The Fruitless Search for Genes in Psychiatry and Psychology

            The June, 2009 edition of The Journal of the American Medical Association reported the results of a meta-analysis by Neil Risch and his colleagues.[1]  These researchers showed that a 2003 study by Caspi and colleagues, where the investigators believed they had found a genetic variant associated with depression when combined with stressful life events, did not stand up to replication attempts. Caspi and colleagues' original study had been widely reported in the media and elsewhere as constituting a major genetic discovery in psychiatry.[2]   

            However, to the critical observers of genetic research in psychiatry and psychology, including those who had pointed to several glaring problems in Caspi and colleaguesÕ study, the failure to replicate these results came as no surprise at all. [3]  This study merely suffered the same fate as other gene-finding claims in psychiatry over the past thirty-five years, such as the much publicized yet subsequently non-replicated claims of nearly a generation ago for bipolar disorder, and for schizophrenia.[4]  Clearly, some type of systematic error is common to these subsequently unsubstantiated findings.

            Previously, a group of leading psychiatric genetic researchers had recognized in 2008, "It is no secret that our field has published thousands of candidate gene association studies but few replicated findings."[5] And in the same year behavioral geneticist Robert Plomin and his colleagues could not cite any substantiated gene findings for personality or IQ (cognitive ability).[6]  A pair of  personality trait molecular genetic researchers wrote in 2009 that their field "has evidently not escaped the conundrum of non-replication that continues to plague the genetics of complex human phenotypes,"[7] and the authors of a 2010 article on cognitive ability and genetics noted, "it is difficult to name even one genetic locus that is reliably associated with normal-range intelligence in young, healthy adultsÉ"[8]  Risch and colleagues concluded that "few if any of the genes identified in candidate gene association studies of psychiatric disorders have withstood the test of replication." They further concluded:

Despite progress in risk gene identification for several complex diseases, few disorders have proven as resistant to robust gene finding as psychiatric illnesses. The slow rate of progress in psychiatry and behavioral sciences partly reflects a still-evolving classification system, absence of valid pathognomonic diagnostic markers, and lack of well-defined etiologic pathways. Although these disorders have long been assumed to result from some combination of genetic vulnerability and environmental exposure, direct evidence from a specific example has not been forthcoming.[9]

 

            Thus, the fields of behavioral genetics and psychiatric genetics are rapidly approaching a period of crisis and re-examination

            There are two broad explanations for the ongoing failure to discover genes in psychiatry and psychology. The first, which is favored by genetic researchers and their backers, is that genes for "complex disorders" exist (although each gene may be of small effect size) and will be discovered once researchers improve their methods and increase their sample sizes. The second explanation, though rarely considered in mainstream works, is that genes for psychiatric disorders and for normal variation in psychological traits do not exist. The latter explanation is consistent with Latham and Wilson's position that, apart from a few exceptions, "genetic predispositions as significant factors in the prevalence of [most] common diseases are refuted," and that the "dearth of disease-causing genes is without question a scientific discovery of tremendous significance."[10] 

            Over the past two decades the popular and scientific literature has been filled with discussions of how improved methods in molecular genetic research will lead to gene discoveries. Although we cannot rule out such possibilities, our purpose here is to suggest that the misreading of previous kinship studies of families, twins, and adoptees has led the scientific community to the premature conclusion that genes for psychiatric disorders and psychological trait variation must exist. 

            In the past few years, molecular genetic researchers have adopted the position of "missing heritability" as an explanation for their failure to discover genes.[11]  The missing heritability interpretation of negative results has been developed in the context of the ongoing failure to uncover most of the genes presumed to underlie common medical disorders, and virtually all of the genes presumed to underlie psychiatric disorders and psychological trait variation. In 2008, Francis Collins, current Director of the U.S. National Institutes of Health and former Director of the National Center for Human Genome Research, stated that missing heritability "is the big topic in the genetics of common disease right now."[12]  Subsequently, the topic has grown even bigger.[13]

            Heritability is "missing," according to one group of prominent researchers, because genome-wide association (GWA) studies "have explained relatively little of the heritability of most complex traits, and the [gene] variants identified through these studies have small effects."[14] A prominent group of researchers (including Francis Collins) headed by Teri Manolio,  Director of the U. S. Office of Population Genomics, published a 2009 article in Nature entitled, "Finding The Missing Heritability."[15] This article has since served as a reference point for molecular genetic researchers, including those in psychiatry and psychology, who have attempted to come to terms with decades of negative results. Manolio and colleagues recognized that only a few gene variants had been discovered for non-psychiatric medical conditions, and pointed to the "the lack of variants detected so far for some neuropsychiatric conditions." They had no doubt that the problem is missing heritability, as opposed to non-existent heritability, because "a substantial proportion of individual differences in disease susceptibility is known to be due to genetic factors." Manolio et al. saw missing heritability as the "'dark matter' of genome-wide association in the sense that one is sure it exists, can detect its influence, but simply cannot 'see' it (yet)."[16] 

            The reason that scientists are certain that "missing" genes exist and await discovery is their belief that previous family, twin, and adoption studies have provided conclusive evidence that genetic factors play a major role. But even if researchers eventually discover specific genes that play a role in intelligence or personality, or that predispose some people to develop psychiatric  disorders, society could still choose to focus attention on changing psychologically unhealthy family, social, and political arrangements that impede human growth and learning, and that contribute to emotional problems and psychiatric disorders. Genetic determinist ideas divert society's attention from these environmental conditions, and shift blame onto people's brains and bodies. Even in the case of medical disorders such as type 2 diabetes, where poverty and malnutrition are well known causes, supporters of genetic determinism continue to press for research dollars to be directed towards genetic research, as opposed to improving social and health conditions.[17]

            Kinship studies of families, twins, and adoptees are known collectively as "quantitative genetic research." While constituting a necessary first step, family studies are widely seen as being unable to disentangle the potential role of genetic and environmental factors. Because family members share a common environment as well as common genes,  finding that a trait "runs in the family" can be explained on either genetic or environmental grounds. As Plomin and colleagues recognized, "Many behaviors 'run in families,' but family resemblance can be due to either nature or nurture."[18] They concluded, correctly in our view, that "[f]amily studies by themselves cannot disentangle genetic and environmental influences."[19]

Twin Studies

            Twin studies and adoption studies, which have been carried out since the 1920s, constitute the main quantitative genetic results cited in support of genetics. We will touch on some problem areas in adoption research later, but for now we focus on twin studies, which provide the most frequently cited evidence in support of important genetic influences on psychiatric disorders and variations in "normally distributed" traits such as IQ and personality. There are two main types of twin research methods: studies of twins reared-together, and studies of twins reared-apart.

            Reared-Together Twins. Studies of twins reared-together, which use a technique called the "twin method," compare the trait resemblance of reared-together monozygotic (MZ) versus reared-together same-sex dizygotic (DZ) twin pairs. If monozygotic pairs resemble each other more than dizygotic pairs (on the basis of correlations or concordance rates), twin researchers conclude that the trait has a genetic component, and then go on to calculate heritability estimates based on the magnitude of the difference. They reach this conclusion on the basis of several theoretical assumptions about twins, the most important and controversial of which is the assumption that MZ and same-sex DZ twin pairs experience roughly equal environments. This is known as the "equal environment assumption" (EEA). The logic appears straightforward, since MZ pairs share a 100% genetic similarity, whereas DZs share only 50% of their genes on average.

            There is, however, a fatal flaw in this logic: The equal environment assumption of the twin method is obviously not correct, since most research in this area finds that MZ twin pairs experience much more similar environments than do DZ pairs.[20]  Moreover, because they are more similar genetically, MZ pairs resemble each other more anatomically than DZ pairs, and this clearly will elicit different treatment from the social environment.[21] Therefore, a plausible interpretation of twin method findings is that the greater psychological trait resemblance of MZ versus DZ twin pairs, a result found by most twin researchers, is completely explainable on the basis of non-genetic factors related to MZ pairs' greater environmental and treatment similarity. From the standpoint of environmental confounds, the twin method has precisely the same problem as family studies because in both, the comparison groups experience far different environments.

            Interestingly, most contemporary twin researchers recognize that the environments experienced by MZ pairs are more similar than those experienced by DZs.[22]  However, on the basis of two main arguments, they continue to hold that the EEA is valid and that the twin method reliably measures genetic influences.

            The first argument is that, although MZ and DZ environments are different, these environments must be shown to differ in aspects relevant to the trait in question. Furthermore, twin researchers often implicitly or explicitly suggest that twin method critics bear the burden of proof for demonstrating that these admittedly unequal environments differ on trait relevant dimensions.[23]

            The second argument twin researchers put forward in defense of EEA and the twin method is that MZ pairs tend to "create" or "elicit" more similar environments for themselves by virtue of their greater genetically-caused similarity of behavior.[24]   For example, according to one group of behavioral genetic researchers, although MZ twins "may well be treated more similarly" than DZs, "this is far more a consequence of their genetic similarity in behaviour (and of ensuing responses by parents and others) than a cause of such similarity."[25] And in 2009, behavioral geneticists Segal and Johnson wrote, "It is important to note that if MZ twins are treated more alike than DZ twins, it is most likely associated with their genetically based behavioral similarities."[26] 

            Regarding the first argument, the proponents of a scientific theory or technique, rather than their critics, bear the burden of proof for showing that their theory or technique is correct.[27] Although twin researchers have carried out a series of tests of the equal environment assumption, these studies have done little to uphold the validity of the twin method.[28]  Ironically, although EEA test researchers usually conclude that their findings support the EEA, most find that MZ twin pairs experience much more similar environments than do DZ pairs. What they fail to understand is that the differing environments that automatically and without qualification invalidate genetic interpretations of  family studies also invalidate genetic interpretations of twin method data.    

            We have seen that the second argument modern twin researchers put forward in defense of the twin method is that MZ twin pair environments are more similar than those of DZ pairs because MZs "create" more similar environments for themselves on the basis of their greater genetic similarity. However, researchers putting forward this "twins create their own environment" position use circular reasoning, in that they assume the very thing they need to demonstrate. According to the Penguin Dictionary of Psychology, circular reasoning is "Empty reasoning in which the conclusion rests on an assumption whose validity is dependent on the conclusion."[29]   Twin researchers have used "empty reasoning" of this type since the 1950s to validate the twin method,  as they circularly assume that twinsÕ behavioral resemblance is caused by genetics in order to conclude that twinsÕ behavioral resemblance is caused by genetics.[30]  Thus the only relevant question in determining the validity of the EEA and the twin method is whether—not why—MZ pairs experience more similar environments than those experienced by DZ pairs.[31] 

            Buried within the schizophrenia twin research literature, which is frequently cited in support of a genetic basis for the condition, is a finding that the pooled concordance rate for same-sex DZ twin pairs is 2-3 times greater than that of opposite-sexed DZ pairs (11.3% vs. 4.7%).[32]  Because the genetic relationship of same-sex and opposite-sex DZ twin pairs is the same, from the genetic standpoint we should find no significant difference between these pooled rates.[33] Moreover, the pooled schizophrenia concordance rate for DZ twins is almost double what it is for ordinary (non-twin) siblings, despite the fact that the genetic relationship between DZ twins and ordinary sibling pairs is the same.[34] These findings are consistent with non-genetic explanations of the causes of schizophrenia, since pairs who share the same degree of genetic relatedness, but who experience more similar environments and a closer emotional bond, are consistently more concordant for schizophrenia than are pairs experiencing less similar environments and a weaker emotional bond. These results provide additional evidence that—as we have seen with family studies—the twin method is unable to disentangle potential genetic and environmental causes of schizophrenia and other psychiatric disorders.[35]

Thus, there are two main conclusions one can reach on the basis of twin method data:[36]

      (1) Contemporary Twin ResearchersÕ Conclusion: The greater resemblance of MZ vs. same-sex DZ twin pairs provides solid evidence that a sizable portion the population variance for psychiatric disorders and psychological traits can be          explained by genetic factors, or

 

      (2) Twin Method CriticsÕ Conclusion: The twin method is a faulty instrument   for assessing the role of genetics, given the likelihood that MZ vs. same-sex DZ        comparisons measure environmental rather than genetic influences. Therefore, all   previous interpretations of the twin method's results in support of genetics are          potentially wrong.

 

            We argue here that the available evidence calls for the acceptance of Conclusion #2, and we agree with three generations of critics who have written that the twin method is no more able than a family study disentangle the potential roles of nature and nurture. As the Nobel Prize winning chemist Wilhelm Ostwald wisely lectured his students in the early 20th century, "Among scientific articles there are to be found not a few wherein the logic and mathematics are faultless but which are for all that worthless, because the assumptions and hypotheses upon which the faultless logic and mathematics rest do not correspond to actuality."[37] 

            Reared-Apart Twins. Because many scientists and commentators have had doubts about the validity of the twin method, some have pointed to studies of twins reared-apart (TRA studies), such as the Minnesota TRA research published by Bouchard and colleagues.[38]  These investigations look mainly at psychological traits such as IQ and personality. However, problems with the methodology and underlying logic of these studies have been outlined by several reviewers.[39] Problem areas include: (1) it is doubtful that most reared-apart MZ pairs (known as MZAs) deserve the status of having been "reared-apart," since most pairs had significant contact with each other for many years; (2) in several studies, there were biases favoring the recruitment of MZA pairs who resembled each other more for behavioral traits than MZA pairs as a population; (3) there is controversy about whether "intelligence" and "personality" are valid and quantifiable constructs; (4) the Minnesota researchers failed to publish life history information for the twins under study, and then denied independent reviewers access to raw data and other unpublished information; and (5) there was likely researcher bias in favor of genetic explanations of the data. [40]            

            Perhaps the most important problem is the original TRA researchers' failure to control for several critical environmental influences shared by MZA pairs, including even those extremely rare cases in which studied MZA pairs were reared apart since early life and grew up without knowing that they had a twin sibling.[41]  In the study containing the highest percentage of MZA pairs of this type, the author found,

            In all 12 pairs there were marked intra-pair differences in that part of the personality         governing immediate psychological interaction and ordinary human intercourse. . . . the   twins behaved, on the whole, very differently, especially in their cooperation, and in their             form of and need for contact. Corresponding with these observations, the twins gave, as a           rule, expression to very different attitudes to life, and very divergent views on general             culture, religion and social problems. Their fields of interest, too, were very different. . . . Those twins who had children treated, on the whole, their children differently, and their     ideas on upbringing were, as often as not, diametrically opposed. Characterologically, the twins presented differences in their ambitions and in their employment of an aggressive       behavior. Emotionally, there was a deep-going dissimilarity with regard to the             appearance of spontaneous emotional reactions or to the control of affective outbursts.     Various traits of personality found their expression in differences in taste, mode of dress,     hair style, use of cosmetics, the wearing of beard or of glasses.[42]

 

Original descriptions of this type have not prevented the authors of numerous books attempting to popularize genetic research, exemplified by Steven Pinker's The Blank Slate[43] and Judith Harris's The Nurture Assumption, from claiming that TRA studies and individual stories reported in the media "suggest that genes can cause striking similarities in personality characteristics, even in the face of substantial differences in rearing environments."[44]

 

            Environmental influences shared by even perfectly separated MZA pairs include common age, common sex, common ethnicity, common physical appearance, common socioeconomic class, common culture, and common prenatal environment. Reared-apart twin pairs (as well as genetically unrelated people born at the same time) are subject to the social and historical influences of their birth cohort. As behavioral genetic researcher Richard Rose once observed, "Were one to capitalize on cohort effects by sampling [genetically] unrelated but age-matched pairs, born, say, over a half-century period, the observed similarities in interests, habits, and attitudes might, indeed, be 'astonishing.'"[45]

            Thus, for reasons unrelated to heredity, we should expect to find a much higher Òvideo game playing behaviorÓ correlation in the United States among pairs of randomly selected 11-year-old middle-class Caucasian boys than we would expect to find among randomly selected pairs drawn from the entire 11- to 100-year-old male and female population of the United States.[46] This hypothetical example illustrates one of the central fallacies of TRA studies. (Bouchard and colleagues were the first TRA researchers to address age and sex confounds, but their adjustments were inadequate to deal with this problem.[47])     

            On purely environmental grounds, therefore, we would expect MZA pairs to correlate well above zero for psychological and behavioral traits.[48] This means that the appropriate control group with which to compare MZA correlations would be a group consisting of genetically unrelated pairs of strangers matched on the environmental influences experienced by MZA pairs.[49]   Most previous MZA studies, however, mistakenly used reared-together MZs as controls.[50] Thus we see that, like the twin method, studies of twins reared-apart are subject to their own set of invalidating environmental confounds.

 

Adoption Studies

            Although twin research has been called the "'Rosetta Stone' of behavior genetics," adoption studies are also used to assess the role of genetic influences on various traits and disorders.[51] Adoption studies investigate people who receive the genes of their birthparents, but are reared in the family environment of people with whom they share no genetic relationship. Adoption research originally focused on IQ, and was extended to include personality and psychiatric disorders such as schizophrenia, attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder, and bipolar disorder. In particular, the Danish-American adoption studies are widely cited as having established schizophrenia as a genetic disorder.[52]  Several commentators, however, have pointed to a number of crucial errors and biases in these studies.[53] In Tienari and colleagues' Finnish schizophrenia adoption studies, the researchers concluded that both genes and family environment play important causative roles.[54]

            Like family and twin studies, adoption studies are subject to their own set of environmental confounds and biases which cast doubt on their ability to separate the potential influences of nature and nurture. Included among these biases are late separation (and accompanying attachment disturbance), range restriction,  whether adoptees and family members are representative of their respective populations, and the selective placement of adoptees.[55]

Tienari and colleagues investigated the adoptive families of Finnish adoptees whose biological mothers were diagnosed with schizophrenia, and the adoptive families of control adoptees, whose biological mothers were not so diagnosed.[56] Although 7% of the index adoptees became psychotic, in contrast to 1% of the control adoptees (which can be accounted for by selective placement factors, see below), Tienari and colleagues' analysis of the families of index adoptees diagnosed as psychotic reveals that 6 of 43 (14%) adoptees who were reared in "seriously disturbed adoptive families" were diagnosed psychotic. In striking contrast, none of the 48 index adoptees reared in "healthy or mildly disturbed adoptive families" was diagnosed psychotic. Moreover, 19 of the 32 adoptees (60%; index and control combined) raised in "severe disturbance" Finnish adoptive families developed a major psychological dysfunction (which included "character disorders," "borderline syndrome," and "psychotic"), whereas none of the 15 adoptees reared in Finnish "healthy" adoptive families developed such a dysfunction.[57]

Looking more closely at the "no selective placement assumption" of adoption studies, psychiatric adoption researchers must assume that factors relating to the adoption process did not lead agencies to place certain groups of adoptees into environments contributing to a higher rate of the disorder in question. However, the evidence suggests that adoption studies of schizophrenia were confounded by environmental factors on the basis of the perceived genetic undesirability of adoptees with a biological family history of mental disorders placed in early-to-mid 20th century Europe.[58]

For example, Finland (like Denmark) had a long history of eugenics-inspired legislation aimed at curbing the reproduction of "hereditarily tainted" people.[59] The Finnish government created a commission in 1926 to study the possibility of sterilizing people seen as "mentally retarded," "mentally ill," or epileptic. In 1935, the Finnish parliament passed the Sterilization Act, which allowed the compulsory eugenic sterilization of "idiots," "imbeciles," and the 'insane," which included people diagnosed with schizophrenia and manic-depression. In fact, compulsory eugenic sterilization was not abolished in Finland until 1970. The Finnish adoptees Tienari and colleagues studied were born between 1927 and 1979, and were therefore placed in an era in which the biological offspring of people diagnosed with a psychotic disorder were seen as undesirable "tainted" adoptees. Clearly, few prospective Finnish adoptive parents would have wanted to adopt such a child.

Selective placement has also been identified as a confounding factor in IQ adoption research, since adoption agencies frequently attempt to match adoptees and adoptive families for socioeconomic status, in addition matching on the basis of the assumed intelligence potential of the adoptee.[60]

Thus, despite adoption studies' theoretical potential to disentangle genetic and environmental influences, most adoption studies published to date have been plagued by methodological problems and potential environmental confounds.

            However, it is possible that a well-designed adoption study could disentangle genetic and environmental factors and put the nature-nurture issue to the test. The researchers performing such a study must, at a minimum, (1) choose as participants only those adoptees who were placed into their adoptive homes at or shortly after birth; (2) determine in advance, and publish or submit to a research register prior to undertaking the study, the specific hypotheses, methods, definitions, and comparison groups that will be used; (3) make a serious attempt to come to grips with problems such as selective placement and range restriction, and be willing to refrain from concluding in favor of genetics if such problems are found; (4) publish, or place with a research register, raw case history information and data relating to participants, and make this data and information available to qualified reviewers for inspection; (5) ensure that all interviews, tests, diagnoses, and ratings are performed blindly, and (6) study only those traits and disorders whose reliability and validity have been demonstrated by previous research.[61]

 

 

Conclusions About the Genetic Paradigm and the Need for an Alternative

            We have suggested that the body of quantitative genetic research in psychiatry and psychology is contaminated by environmental factors.[62] In addition, these studies contain many glaring methodological problems and other biases. Although the relatives in these studies frequently manifest traits and disorders in patterns predicted by genetic theories, these patterns usually match the predictions made by theories of non-genetic causation as well.[63]   Thus, it is likely that family, twin, and adoption studies have been unable to disentangle the potential roles of genetic and environmental influences on traits and disorders, and that the researchers who typically perform this research have greatly underestimated the potential role of environmental confounds. It has been left to critics to focus on these problems, yet their voices have been lost in the vast literature produced in the past few decades by authors claiming major genetic influences on these traits.

            We call on researchers in psychiatry and psychology, and other behavioral scientists, to suspend the current "missing heritability" interpretation of negative molecular genetic findings and to embark on a serious reassessment of the validity of twin and adoption studies. Latham and Wilson concluded that a reasonable interpretation of the failure to identify genes is that "heritability studies of twins are inherently mistaken or misinterpreted," and that the "dark matter" of missing heritability "becomes simply an artifact arising from overinterpretation of twin studies." 

            In 1994, behavioral geneticists Robert Plomin, Michael Owen, and Peter McGuffin wrote in  Science of a genetic variant associated with AlzheimerÕs Disease, and continued, "We predict that QTL [quantitative trait loci, or genes of various effect sizes] associations will soon be found for other complex human behaviors."[64]  However, this prediction has turned out to be wrong.[65]  Indeed, three genetically-oriented Nobel prize winning researchers and their colleagues, in a 2010 "Policy Forum" article also appearing in Science, recognized the "frustrating lack of progress" in understanding the genetics of mental disorders.[66]     

A final issue to consider is the broader context of genetic research into psychiatric disorders.  This context includes scientific and social issues that form the assumptions which guide this work; the context also includes the scientific and social consequences of this work. This inquiry into the context of research is a branch of philosophy of science known as Social Studies of Science. It is pursued in The Society for Social Studies of Science, and in journals such as Social Epistemology and Social Studies of Science. The social and intellectual context affects the quality of particular research (just as social context affects all behavior). It is also an important avenue for assessing the plausibility and validity of the research.

           Research into possible genetic causes of psychiatric disorders partakes of a system of superordionate scientific issues. These include the nature of human psychology and its relation to biochemical mechanisms. If genes cause psychiatric disorders in some specific manner then they must work through biochemical mechanisms. This raises the broader, superordinate question whether psychiatric disorders are caused by (reducible to) biochemical mechanisms – i.e., how can biochemical mechanisms cause someone to experience particular symptoms of, for example,  depression, eating disorders, risky behavior, or social phobia? This question about biochemical mechanisms and psychiatric disorders depends upon a still broader, superordinate question of whether psychology in general is determined by biochemical mechanisms. Research into these two superordinate questions strengthens or weakens the genetic hypothesis of psychiatric disorders. If research demonstrates that psychology is not determined by biochemical mechanisms, then psychiatric disorders cannot be determined by genes.[67] Conversely, research into the subordinate issue of whether genes cause psychiatric disorders strengthens or weakens the superordinate issues. Researchers and the authors of authoritative textbooks who claim that genes play a major role in causing psychiatric disorders help strengthen superordinate theories that these disorders have biochemical causes, and that psychology has biochemical causes.

        While pursuing these corollary issues is outside the bounds of this chapter, we recommend that readers do so in order to better understand the question of genetic causes of psychiatric disorders. We believe that research into these issues will support the rejection of the genetic paradigm of psychiatric disorders, and will give grounds for an alternative paradigm that emphasizes the role of familial, social, cultural, and political influences. The reason that research has failed to demonstrate genetic influences on mental illness is because the genetic, naturalistic paradigm of mental illness is wrong.   

            In a 2000 article entitled "Three Laws of Behavioral Genetics and What They Mean," behavioral geneticist Eric Turkheimer concluded, mainly on the basis of twin studies, that "all human behavioral traits are heritable."[68] At that time, behavioral genetic and psychiatric genetic researchers believed that the completion of the Human Genome Project would rapidly lead to gene discoveries.[69] So did Turkheimer, who wrote that "Behavior geneticists anticipate vindication" by the discovery of genes causing behavioral variation. On the other hand, wrote Turkheimer,

            Critics of behavior genetics expect the opposite, pointing to the repeated failures to           replicate associations between genes and behavior as evidence of the shaky             theoretical underpinnings of which they have so long complained.[70] 

 

A dozen years later the critics indeed appear to have been vindicated, and the real problem may well be, as Turkheimer described it, the "shaky theoretical underpinnings" provided by genetic theories based on family, twin, and adoption studies.


 

       

                   



[1] N. Risch, R. Herrell, T. Lehner, et al., "Interaction Between the Serotonin Transporter Gene (5-HTTLPR), Stressful Life Events, and Risk of Depression," JAMA 301 (2009): 2462-2471.

 

[2] A. Caspi, K. Sugden, T. E. Moffitt, et al., "Influence of Life Stress on Depression: Moderation By a Polymorphism in the 5-HTT Gene," Science 301 (2003): 386-389.

 

[3] C. Ratner, "Genes and Psychology In the News," New Ideas in Psychology 22 (2004): 29-47.

 

[4] J. Egland, D. S. Gerhard, D. L. Pauls, J. N. Sussex, and K. K. Kidd, "Bipolar Affective Disorders Linked to DNA Markers on Chromosome 11," Nature 325 (1987): 783-787. R. Sherrington, J. Brynjolfsson, H. Petursson, et al., "Localization of a Susceptibility Locus for Schizophrenia on Chromosome 5," Nature 336 (1988): 164-167.

 

[5] S.V. Faraone, J. W. Smoller, C. N. Pato, P. Sullivan, and M. T. Tsuang, "The New Neuropsychiatric Genetics," American Journal of Medical Genetics Part B (Neuropsychiatric Gen.) 147B (2008, p. 1): 1-2.

 

[6] Robert Plomin, J. C. DeFries, G. E. McClearn, and P. McGuffin, Behavioral Genetics, 4th Ed. (New York: Worth, 2008).

 

[7] R. P. Ebstein and S. Israel, "Molecular Genetics of Personality: How Our Genes can Bring us to a Better Understanding of Why We Act the Way We Do," ed. Yong-Kyu Kim, Handbook of Behavior Genetics (New York: Springer, 2009, p. 240),  239-250. See also K. J. H. Verweij, B. P.  Zietsch, S. Medland, et al., "A Genome-Wide Association Study of CloningerÕs Temperament Scales: Implications for the Evolutionary Genetics of Personality." Biological Psychology  85 (2010): 306-317.    

 

[8] I. J. Deary, L. Penke, and W. Johnson, "The Neuroscience of Human Intelligence Differences." Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11 (2010, p. 205): 201-211.

 

[9] Risch et al., "Interaction," 2463. The term "pathognomonic" in this case refers to a biological marker characteristic or indicative of a particular disease.

 

 

[10] J. Latham and A. Wilson, "The Great DNA Data Deficit: Are Genes for Disease a Mirage?" The Bioscience Research Project (2010; retrieved online 12/18/10 from http://www.bioscienceresource.org/commentaries/article.php?id=46 )

 

[11] E. S. Gershon, N. Alliey-Rodriguez, and C. Liu, "After GWAS: Searching for Genetic Risk for Schizophrenia and Bipolar Disorder," American Journal of Psychiatry 168 (2011): 253-256; E. S. Lander, "Initial Impact of the Sequencing of the Human Genome," Nature 470 (2011): 187-197; B. Maher, "The Case of the Missing Heritability," Nature 456 (2008): 18-21; T. A. Manolio, F. S. Collins,  N. J. Cox, et al., "Finding the Missing Heritability of Complex Diseases," Nature 461 (2009): 747-753.

[12] Maher, "Case," 18.

[13] Gershon et al., "After GWAS."

[14] E. E. Eichler, J. Flint, G. Gibson, et al., "Missing Heritability and Strategies for Finding the Underlying Causes of Complex Disease," Nature Reviews Genetics 11 (2010, p. 446): 446-450.

[15] Manolio et al., "Finding."

[16] Manolio et al., "Finding," 748.

[17] C. Chaufan, "How Much Can a Large Population Study on Genes, Environments, Their Interactions and Common Diseases Contribute to the Health of the American People?" Social Science and Medicine  65 (2007): 1730–1741. 

[18] Plomin et al., "Behavioral Genetics," 70.

[19] Plomin et al., "Behavioral Genetics," 151.

 

[20] Jay Joseph, The Gene Illusion: Genetic Research in Psychiatry and Psychology Under the Microscope (New York: Algora, 2004; 2003 United Kingdom Edition by PCCS Books); Jay Joseph, The Missing Gene: Psychiatry, Heredity, and the Fruitless Search for Genes (New York: Algora, 2006); K. Kendler, "Overview: A Current Perspective on Twin Studies of Schizophrenia," American Journal of Psychiatry 140 (1983): 1413-1425.

 

[21] Although many twin researchers believe that treatment similarity based on physical appearance should be counted as a genetic effect, and therefore does not violate the equal environment assumption of the twin method, the physical resemblance of monozygotic twin pairs is the result of the splitting of a fertilized egg. Thus, although this physical resemblance is based on the pair's identical genotype, it is not an inherited characteristic because the same physical resemblance would be present regardless of who their biological parents are, or in whose womb they develop. See J. Joseph, "The Equal Environment Assumption of the Classical Twin Method: A Critical Analysis," Journal of Mind and Behavior 19 (1998): 325-358.

 

[22] T. J. Bouchard, Jr. and M. McGue, "Genetic and Environmental Influences on Human Psychological Differences," Journal of Neurobiology  54 (2003): 4-45;  Kendler, "Overview," David Rowe, The Limits of Family Influence: Genes, Experience, and Behavior (New York: Guilford, 1994).

 

[23] M. J. Lyons, K. Kendler, A. Provet, and M. T. Tsuang, "The Genetics of Schizophrenia," in Genetic Issues in Psychosocial Epidemiology, eds. M. Tsuang, K. Kendler, M. Lyons (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1991), 119-153; J. R. Alford, C. L. Funk, and J. R. Hibbing, "Beyond Liberals and Conservatives to Political Genotypes and Phenotypes," Perspectives on Politics 6 (2008): 321-328.

 

[24] Kendler, "Overview"; S. Scarr and L. Carter-Saltzman, "Twin Method: Defense of a Critical Assumption," Behavior Genetics 9 (1979): 527-542;  J. H. Fowler, L. A. Baker, and C.T. Dawes, "Genetic Variation in Political Participation," American Political Science Review 102 (2008): 233–248.

 

[25] D. A. Hay, M. McStephen, and F. Levy, "Introduction to the Genetic Analysis of Attentional Disorders," in Attention, Genes, and ADHD, eds. F. Levy and D. Hay (East Sussex, UK: Brunner-Routledge, 2001), 7-34.

 

[26] N. L. Segal and W. Johnson, "Twin Studies of General Mental Ability," In Handbook of Behavior Genetics, ed. Y. Kim (New York: Springer, 2009, p. 82), 81-89.

 

[27] S. O. Lilienfeld, S. J. Lynn, and J. M. Lohr, "Science and Pseudoscience in Clinical Psychology: Initial Thoughts, Reflections, and Considerations," in Science and Pseudoscience in Clinical Psychology, eds. S. Lilienfeld, S. Lynn, and J. Lohr (New York: Guilford, 2003), 1-14.

 

[28] Joseph, "Missing Gene"; A. Pam, S. S. Kemker, C. A. Ross, and R. Golden, "The 'Equal Environment Assumption' in MZ-DZ Comparisons: An Untenable Premise of Psychiatric Genetics?" Acta Geneticae Medicae et Gemellologiae 45 (1996): 349-360.    

 

[29] A. S. Reber, The Penguin Dictionary of Psychology  (London: Penguin, 1985, p. 123).   

 

[30] J. Joseph, "Genetic Research in Psychiatry and Psychology: A Critical Overview,"  Handbook of Developmental Science, Behavior, and Genetics, eds. K. Hood, C. Tucker Halpern, G. Greenberg, R. Lerner, Eds., (Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010), 557-625.

One of the first attempts to use the "twins create their own environment" argument is support of the twin method was by James Shields in 1954, who wrote, "In so far as binovular [DZ] twins are treated differently from one another and more differently than uniovular [MZ] twins, this is likely to be due, not so much to causes outside the twins as to innate differences in the needs of the binovular twins themselves, manifested by different patterns of behaviour." J. Shields,   "Personality Differences and Neurotic Traits in Normal Twin Schoolchildren," Eugenics Review 45 (1954, p. 240): 213-246.  Other examples of researchers invoking this argument since the 1950s include F. J. Kallmann, "The Uses of Genetics in Psychiatry,"  Journal of Mental Science 104 (1958): 542-552; S. V. Vandenberg, "Contributions of Twin Research to Psychology," Psychological Bulletin 66 (1966): 327-352; J. C. Loehlin and R. C. Nichols, Heredity, Environment, and Personality  (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1976); K. S. Kendler, "The Genetics of Schizophrenia: A Current Perspective," Psychopharmacology: The Third Generation of Progress, ed.  H. Meltzer (New York: Raven Press, 1987), pp. 705-713; Rowe, "Limits."

 

[31] Joseph, "Gene Illusion."  

[32] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; Joseph, "Missing Gene."

[33] D. Jackson, "A Critique of the Literature on the Genetics of Schizophrenia,"  The Etiology of Schizophrenia, ed. D. Jackson (New York: Basic, 1960), 33-87.

 

[34] I. I. Gottesman, Schizophrenia Genesis. (New York: Freeman, 1991).

 

[35] Jackson, "Critique of the Literature"; Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; C. Ratner, VygotskyÕs Sociohistorical Psychology and Its Contemporary Applications (New York: Plenum, 1991).

 

[36] J. Joseph, "The Genetics of Political Attitudes and Behavior: Claims and Refutations," Ethical Human Psychology and Psychiatry, 12 (2010): 200-217.

 

[37] Quoted in L. Hogben, Nature and Nurture. (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1933, p. 121).

 

[38] T. J. Bouchard, Jr., D. T. Lykken, and M. McGue, et al., "Sources of Human Psychological Differences: The Minnesota Study of Twins Reared Apart," Science 250 (1990): 223-228.

 

[39] S. L. Farber, Identical Twins Reared Apart: A Reanalysis. (New York: Basic, 1981); J. Joseph, "Separated Twins and the Genetics of Personality Differences: A Critique," American Journal of Psychology 114 (2001): 1-30; Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; L. Kamin, The Science and Politics of I.Q. (Potomac, MD: Erlbaum, 1974); L. J. Kamin and A. S. Goldberger, "Twin Studies in Behavioral Research: A Skeptical View," Theoretical Population Biology 61 (2002): 83-95; H. F. Taylor,  The IQ Game: A Methodological Inquiry into the Heredity-Environment Controversy  (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1980).

 

[40] Joseph, "Gene Illusion."

 

[41] Farber, "Identical Twins."

 

[42] N. Juel-Nielsen, Individual and Environment: Monozygotic Twins Reared Apart. (New York: International Universities Press ,1965/1980, rev ed., p. 75), italics in original.   

 

[43] S. Pinker, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (New York: Viking, 2002, p. 33).

 

[44] J. R. Harris, The Nurture Assumption: Why Children Turn Out the Way They Do (New York: Touchstone, 1998), 33.

 

[45] R. J. Rose, "Separated Twins: Data and Their Limits," Science  215 (1982): 959-960.

 

[46] Joseph, "Genetic Research Overview."

 

[47] M. McGue and T. J. Bouchard, Jr., "Adjustment of Twin Data for the Effects of Age and Sex," Behavior Genetics 14 (1984): 325-343. 

 

[48] Taking a different approach with a pair sharing only common age, common sex, and a prenatal environment, we could imagine a hypothetical pair of separated-at-birth Arab-American female MZAs born in Berkeley, California. One twin is raised in a liberal non-religious Berkeley family, while the other is sent to Saudi Arabia and is raised there in a conservative Islamic Saudi Arabian family, and they have no contact with each other and do not know of each other's existence.  In Saudi Arabia, women experience "gender apartheid" in a strict Islamic society, are not allowed to interact with men much of the time, and are required to be covered in black from head to toe when in public. If these twins are reunited for the first time at age 40, how much would we expect them to have in common?

 

[49] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; Joseph, "Genetic Research Overview."

 

[50] For example, See Bouchard et al., "Sources," 226, Table 4.

 

[51] T. J. Bouchard, "Forward" in N. Segal, Entwined Lives. (New York: Dutton, 1999, p. ix): ix-x.

 

[52] S. S. Kety, D. Rosenthal, P. H. Wender, and F. Schulsinger, "The Types and Prevalence of Mental Illness in the Biological and Adoptive Families of Adopted Schizophrenics," in The Transmission of Schizophrenia, eds. D. Rosenthal and S. Kety (New York: Pergamon, 1968): 345-362;  S. S. Kety, P. H. Wender, B. Jacobsen, et al., "Mental Illness in the Biological and Adoptive Relatives of Schizophrenic Adoptees: Replication of the Copenhagen Study to the Rest of Denmark," Archives of General Psychiatry 51 (1994): 442-455.

 

[53] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; Joseph, "Missing Gene"; T. Lidz, "Commentary on a Critical Review of Recent Adoption, Twin, and Family Studies of Schizophrenia: Behavioral Genetics Perspective," Schizophrenia Bulletin  2 (1976): 402-412;  T. Lidz and S. Blatt, "Critique of the Danish-American Studies of the Biological and Adoptive Relatives of Adoptees who Became Schizophrenic," American Journal of Psychiatry 140 (1983): 426-435; T. Lidz, S. Blatt, and B. Cook, "Critique of the Danish-American Studies of the Adopted-Away Offspring of Schizophrenic Parents," American Journal of Psychiatry, 138 (1981): 1063-1068;  R. C. Lewontin, S. Rose, and L. J. Kamin, Not in Our Genes (New York: Pantheon, 1984).

 

[54] P. Tienari, A. Sorri, I. Lahti, et al.,  "Genetic and Psychosocial Factors in Schizophrenia: The Finnish Adoptive Family Study," Schizophrenia Bulletin  13 (1987): 477-484.

 

[55] M. Stoolmiller, "Implications of the Restricted Range of Family Environments for Estimates of Heritability and Nonshared Environment in Behavior-Genetic Adoption Studies," Psychological Bulletin 125 (1999): 392-409;  Plomin et al., "Behavioral Genetics";  M. Rutter, Genes and Behavior: Nature-Nurture Interplay Explained (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006).

 

[56] P. Tienari, I. Lahti, A. Sorri, et al., "The Finnish Adoptive Family Study of Schizophrenia: Possible Joint Effects of Genetic Vulnerability and Family Interaction," in Understanding Major Mental Disorder: The Contribution of Family Interaction Research, eds. K. Halweg and M. Goldstein (New York: Family Process Press, 1987): 33-54. 

 

[57] Tienari et al., "Finnish Adoptive Family Study"; Ratner, "VygotskyÕs Sociohistorical,"

 

[58] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; Joseph, "Missing Gene"; Lewontin et al., "Not in Our Genes."

 

[59] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; E. Hemminki, A. Rasimus, and E. Forssas, "Sterilization in Finland: From Eugenics to Contraception," Social Science and Medicine 45 (1997): 1875-1884; M. Hietala, "From Race Hygiene to Sterilization: The Eugenics Movement in Finland," in Eugenics and the Welfare State: Sterilization Policy in Denmark, Sweden, Norway, and Finland, eds. G. Broberg and N. Roll-Hansen (East Lansing, Michigan: Michigan State University Press, 1996), 195-258. 

 

[60] Kamin, "Science and Politics"; L. J. Kamin, in H. J. Eysenck vs. L. J. Kamin, The Intelligence Controversy. (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1981); H. Munsinger, "The Adopted Child's IQ: A Critical Review," Psychological Bulletin 82 (1975): 623-659.

 

[61] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; J. Joseph and S. Baldwin, "Four Editorial Proposals to Improve Social Sciences Research and Publication," International Journal of Risk and Safety in Medicine 13 (2000): 117-127. 

 

[62] Joseph, "Gene Illusion"; Joseph, "Missing Gene"; Joseph, "Genetic Research Overview."

 

[63] Joseph, "Genetic Research Overview."

 

[64] R. Plomin, M. J. Owen, and P. McGuffin, "The Genetic Basis of Complex Behaviors," Science 264 (1994, p. 1737): 1733-1739.

 

[65] Gershon et al., "Searching"; Joseph, "Genetic Research Overview"; Risch et al., "Interaction Between"; Segal and Johnson, "Twin Studies"; K. J. Verweij, B. P. Zietsch, S. E. Medland, et al., "A Genome-wide Association study of CloningerÕs Temperament Scales: Implications for the Evolutionary Genetics of Personality," Biological Psychology  85 (2010): 306-317.

 

[66] H. Akil, S. Brenner, E. Kandel, K. S. Kendler, M. King, E. Scolnick, J. D. Watson, and  H. Y. Zoghbi, "The Future of Psychiatric Research: Genomes and Neural Circuits," Science  327 (2010): 1580-1581.

 

[67]  See Ratner, "VygotskyÕs Sociohistorical"; C. Ratner, Macro Cultural Psychology: A Political Philosophy of Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), 2011b, and C. Ratner,  "A Cultural-Psychological Analysis of Emotions," Culture and Psychology 6 (2000): 5-39.

 

 

[68] E. Turkheimer, "Three Laws of Behavior Genetics and What They Mean," Current Directions in Psychological Science 9 (2000, p. 160): 160-164.

 

[69] For example, see S. E. Hyman, "Introduction to the Complex Genetics of Mental Disorders," Biological Psychiatry  45 (1999): 518–521;  J. B. Potash and J. R. DePaulo, Jr., "Searching High and Low: A Review of the Genetics of Bipolar Disorder," Bipolar Disorders  2 (2000): 8–26.

.

 

[70] Turkheimer, "Three Laws," 163.