Subjectivism
Subjectivism and subjectivity
Subjectivism is a certain way
of conceptualizing subjectivity. Subjectivity is what makes us subjects rather
than objects. Subjectivity includes processes denoted by the terms mental,
mind, conscious, experience, agency, will, intentionality, thinking, feeling,
remembering, interpreting, understanding, learning, and psyche. These
subjective processes comprise the activity of subjects. Without subjectivity,
we would only be physical objects devoid of activity.
Subjectivity is
understandable if we see how it develops over the phylogenetic scale. Lower
animals' behavior is devoid of subjectivity. It is a direct, immediate
association of a response with a stimulus. The response is determined by a
biological program known as an instinct. More advanced animals progressively
develop subjective processes that mediate between stimuli and responses and
increasingly determine the animal's response to stimuli. Subjectivity reaches
its highest form in humans who think, plan, remember, feel, dream, imagine,
anticipate, symbolize, decide, understand, learn, and initiate action on a
level that is far more sophisticated, complex, and active than any animal's.
Subjective functions determine how we react to stimuli. Stimuli themselves do
not directly determine our reaction, as they do in lower organisms.
For subjectivity to mediate
stimuli it must be different from them. This justifies examining it as a particular
order of things, a distinctive phenomenon. This is what subjectivism does. It
examines the interiority of subjectivity, the active processes that are
subjectivity and which determine behavior.
Subjectivism is one
conception of subjectivity. Subjectivism construes subjectivity as the
product of the subject, or individual. In this view, what we think, imagine,
feel, remember, expect, understand, and strive for are entirely the product of
ourselves. Subjectivity may utilize worldly things, but always on its own
terms, for its own purposes, according to its own processes and laws.
Subjectivism in The Humanities and Social Sciences
Subjectivism has been the
dominant view of subjectivity in many fields of scholarship.
Rene Descartes and Bishop
Berkeley expressed the core notion of subjectivism. Descartes proposed that
mind is distinct from body and world and is a realm of its own. Berkeley
expressed this in his classic statement that the world is as I see it. My
perception does not represent the world. Rather, the world is an expression of
my subjectivity. The processes and principles of my subjectivity determine how
I see the world; the world does not influence my perception of it. The
direction is entirely from inside my mind to the outside world.
Immanuel Kant similarly
proposed that subjectivity cannot know the world because the two are separate
domains. Subjectivity contains its own intrinsic laws, such as ethical
principles, that structure one's perception of the world.
Historical discussions,
especially intellectual history, often present events as the unfolding of ideas
that are freely decided by people. One hears that "the prevailing outlook
changed from a focus on national construction to a more international
outlook." Philosophies, legal concepts, and marriage customs are thought
of as exclusively rooted in thinking, perception, desires, motivation, and
reasoning apart from conditions, structures, and resources.
Subjectivism is also a strong tendency in
a branch of sociology known as micro sociology. Erving Goffman proclaimed his
work to be micro-sociological because it studied face-to-face social
interactions. These he defined as interpersonal, face-to-face environments. His
work is not about social organization and social structure which are the
traditional concerns of sociologists. Anthony Giddens perceptively explains
that Goffman¹s main concern throughout his writings involves individuals
directly attending to what each other are saying and doing for a particular
segment of time. Even when individuals are group members, their interactions
are to be understood in terms of an immediate interpersonal encounter, not in
terms of their membership of the group.
Goffman is not interested, for example, in the role of a doctor in
relation to the wider medical community. His focus on face-to-face encounters
leads him to concentrate on such interpersonal dynamics as mutual eye contact,
body space, and details (³moves²) of the conversation act such as turn taking
(timing), silences, and volume of speaking. This conversation analysis lacks a
relation to the existence of social institutions including
the power relations of who owns and controls them.
Subjectivism is also characteristic of many spiritual
doctrines. Hindu Yoga, for example, is a systematic method of physical postures
and breathing exercises to help concentrate thoughts on a single object to
systematically reduce the diversity and rate of flow of thoughts till it comes
to a near stop. At this stage, a practitioner of Yogic techniques is said to
withdraw attention from the object
of thoughts to thought itself and further on to the self-as-subject at the
centre of the universe of experience. Drawing attention completely to the
self-as-subject epitomizes subjectivism.
Subjectivism in Psychology
Subjectivism takes various
forms in the discipline of psychology.
Jerome Bruner believes that
culture is symbolic meanings. He says that social realities are not bricks that
we trip over or bruise ourselves on when we kick at them, but the meanings that
we achieve by the sharing of human cognitions. In Bruner's world, we do not
encounter and are not bruised by armies, wars, inequality, abuse, exploitation,
pollution, global warming, power, poverty, wealth, disease, the world bank,
congress, the CIA, immigration quotas, emigration restrictions, or prisons.
These are not real things "out there in the world" which directly
affect us. They are simply meanings which become negotiated through
interpersonal communication. We can readily change these concepts by simply
renegotiating them with our colleagues.
Reducing social reality to
symbolic meanings is subjectivism because it construes subjective experience as
a self-contained realm.
Jaan Valsiner espouses a subjectivist view of agency.
Formerly an advocate of Lev Vygotsky¹s sociohistorical psychology, he now asserts that
culture is a set of "suggestions" which individuals can freely
accept, reject, or modify as they wish. Valsiner replaces
sociohistorical psychology with a new formulation called
"co-constructionism." In contrast to sociohistorical psychology which
construes the individual as profoundly affected by culture, co-constructionism
grants primacy to the individual's decision about how to deal with culture.
Acknowledging that his new position is a wholesale rejection of sociocultural
psychology, Valsiner says that the logic of the argument supporting the
relevance of the social environment in human development is reversed in
the co-constructionist paradigm. According to the new paradigm, "most of
human development takes place through active ignoring and neutralization of
most of the social suggestions to which the person is subjected in everyday
life" (Valsiner, 1998, p. 393, emphasis in original).
Valsiner even contends that babies construct their own
personal goals. They utilize culture as an instrumental means for achieving
their own goals; they do not adapt themselves to established culture as social
scientists formerly believed.
Subjectivism in Qualitative Methodology
Subjectivism dominates qualitative methodology. It
construes interactions between researcher and subjects (through interviews in
particular) and the active interpretation of data -- which are central features
of qualitative research -- as a license for the free exercise of subjective
processes. The subject is free to express whatever subjective idea he or she
desires, and the researcher is free to subjectively interpret data.
The subjectivistic tendency in qualitative research
(which is contradicted by an objectivistic tendency that is described in the
entry on objectivism) claims that the world, including the psychological world
of subjects, is unknowable. Consequently, the researcher constructs an
impression of the world as he or she sees it, without regard for whether this
subjective impression corresponds to any reality beyond. The researcher's
subjectivity is a world unto itself, which is the classic definition of
subjectivism. Validity and objectivity are irrelevant issues here, as is
methodology. There is no point developing a rigorous methodology to apprehend
and measure psychological reality because it simply does not exist. Qualitative
research, in this view, consists in researchers developing and comparing their own
accounts of psychology.
This
subjectivist approach to qualitative research is expressed by Ken Gergen's
statement of social constructionism/postmodernism: "There is no means of
declaring that the world is either out there or reflected objectively by an 'in
here'" (Gergen, 2001, p. 805).
The constructionist is not, then, interested in
truth as a scientific outcome—or at least truth with a capital
"T"—a universal or transcendent propositional network. There
may be local truths, established within various scientific fields, within the
various communities of humankind, and these must surely be honored from within
the traditions of these communities. However, the future well-being of the
world community depends on facilitating dialogue among these local traditions.
Declarations of truth beyond tradition are, in this sense, a step toward
tyranny and, ultimately, the end of communication (Gergen, 2004).
To tell the truth, on this account, is not to
furnish an accurate picture of what actually happened but to participate in a
set of social conventions ...To be objective is to play by the rules within a
given tradition of social practices ...To do science is not to hold a mirror to
nature but to participate actively in the interpretive conventions and
practices of a particular culture. The major question that must be asked of
scientific accounts, then, is not whether they are true to nature but what
these accounts ... offer to the culture more generally" (Gergen, 2001, p.
806). "A postmodern empiricism would replace the 'truth game' with a
search for culturally useful theories and findings with significant cultural
meaning (ibid., p. 808). Arguments about what is really real are futile (ibid.,
p. 806).
A strand of feminism
amplifies this by repudiating the notion of a real world of phenomena that can
and should be objectively apprehended. Instead science is equated with the
subjectivity of researchers. These feminists denounce scientific objectivity as
nothing more than a political ideology that is promoted by men to oppress
women. For instance, Liz Stanley & Sue Wise (1983, p. 169) assert that
objectivity is "an excuse for a power relationship every bit as obscene as
the power relationship that leads women to be sexually assaulted, murdered and
otherwise treated as mere objects. The assault on our minds, the removal from
existence of our experiences as valid and true, is every bit as
questionable." Stanley & Wise agree with Gergen's position that
"there are many (often competing) versions of truth. Which, if any, is `the'
truth is irrelevant. And even if such a thing as `truth' exists, this is
undemonstrable" (Stanley & Wise, 1983). This position is
subjectivistic because it places the subjectivity of researchers at the center
of things, and denies worldly phenomena apart from the researcher's
subjectivity.
Subjectivism in qualitative
research additionally accepts subjective accounts of subjects about their
psychology as the object of research. The objective is to validate subjective
interpretations, meanings, and understandings. This line of research does not
seek to explain subjects' subjective accounts in terms of external influences.
For this would deny originality and agency to subjects' subjectivity. Nor does
this line of research seek to evaluate subjects' subjective accounts by
comparing them to other sources of information -- such as other people's
accounts of the same psychological phenomenon. Subjectivistic research would
not compare a child's account of her experience with her parents' account of
her experience -- e.g., the child says she was unhappy five years ago and
resented her parents, while the parents show photographs of the child appearing
very happy with them. For this kind of comparison too would challenge the
originality and agency of the subject's subjective account. It might prove that
the subject misinterpreted her experience or some other event. External data is
eschewed by subjectivistic research because it transcends the pure subjectivity
of the agent.
Howard Garfinkel's
ethnomethodology, for example, abstains from judging peoples' statements as to
their accuracy, adequacy, value, importance, necessity, practicality, success,
or consequences. It only refers to conditions outside individuals when they do.
If subjects do not mention social conditions, they are not introduced by the
researcher. Thus, even if a person objectively fits the category of lower class
(because of her education, occupation, income, family background), she must be
regarded as middle class if this is how she subjectively sees herself.
These features of
subjectivistic research are illustrated in a study by Dorothy Holland on the
ways in which college girls experience romantic love. From interviews, she
reports that some girls pursue romantic love enthusiastically while others are
ambivalent and others reject it. One girl, Sandy, sought romantic love but had
trouble establishing the kind of relationships she wanted with men. She also
learned that a potential boyfriend from back home was involved with someone
else. So she took a stronger interest in friendships and developed a special
friendship with one person. Another girl, Karen, tried to make herself more
attractive by suggesting to her boyfriend that she had many other suitors.
Holland explained these strategies as based on personal decision-making
processes that the subjects employed: These strategies were ones the women
themselves had improvised or decided to use. Holland explains the subjects'
approaches to love as stemming from personal traits such as their
identification of themselves as romantically inclined and skillful. She does
not indicate social reasons, models, values, or practices that might have
influenced the subjects to adopt these strategies for dealing with love.
Discourse analysis, or
discursive psychology, is another approach to research that is strongly
subjectivitistic. It typically treats speech acts as spontaneous constructions
that reflect individual agency and constitute subjectivity. This is
subjectivistic because it construes subjectivity and discourse as spontaneously
created worlds in themselves, uninfluenced by external events. Indeed, social
phenomena are treated as discursive products; speech is not regarded as
denoting worldly events. Culture and psychology are created by people as they
speak; they do not stand over people and influence them. While certain
discourse analysts do link discourse to cultural influences, many treat it as
an entirely subjective process free from external influences or evaluation.
Evaluation of subjectivism
Subjectivism contributes to
our understanding of human subjectivity/psychology because it emphasizes the
active role that these play in generating behavior. Subjectivism prevents us
from regarding people as mechanical, empty responders to stimuli -- as
behaviorism, positivism, and artificial intelligence presume. Subjectivism
corrects the widespread tendency in psychology to mechanically associate
independent and dependent variables, with no consideration for subjects' active
interpretation, comprehension, anticipation. It also corrects social
reductionism -- discussed in the entry on objectivism -- which reduces
psychology to social structures.
Yet this contribution of
subjectivism comes at a price. Emphasizing subjective activity so strongly and
exclusively overlooks social and natural influences on subjectivity/psychology.
Subjectivism eschews the
criterion of validity (objectivity, and truth). This is dangerous because
invalidating the notion of validity prevents invalidating invalid conceptions
and conclusions. Invalidating validity validates invalidity.
A balance can be achieved by
acknowledging the activity of subjectivity along with social constraints that
shape it. For example, in forming personal identity. individuals are highly active in the process of
self-making, however, the materials available for writing one's own story are a
function of our public and shared notions of personhood. American accounts of
the self involve a set of culture-confirming ideas and images of success, competence,
ability, and the need to `feel good'. Although making a self appears to be an
individual and individualizing pursuit, it is also a collective and
collectivizing one.
Cultural influences, content,
and function can be seen in psychological phenomena. They can be seen in
Karen's approach to love that Holland recounted earlier. Karen's strategy of
enhancing her attractiveness by exaggerating her appeal to numerous men bears
striking resemblance to a principle of free market economics -- namely, that increased
demand drives up the value of a commodity. Businessmen often exaggerate the
demand for a product in order to enhance its attractiveness and increase its
price. Employees often exaggerate the number of job offers they have, or could
have, in order to raise the value of their salaries. From Holland's brief
description, Karen evidently imported this common business practice into her
personal world of romantic love.
Subjectivity is permeated by
cultural content, it is not a self-contained realm. This follows from the fact
that subjectivity is oriented toward the world and laden with worldly content.
Subjectivity enhances the organism's comprehension of the world and its ability
to plan effective action within it. A self-contained subjectivity that created
itself ex nihilo without any basis in or regard for the world, would be of
little service to the organism.
See also: Objectivism, social constructionism,
methodological individualism-holism
Further Readings
Branco,
A., & Valsiner, J. (1997). Changing methodologies: A co-constructionist
study of goal orientations in social interactions. Psychology and Developing
Societies, 9, 35-64.
Bruner,
J. (1982). The language of education. Social Research, 49, 835-853.
Gergen, K. ( Sept. 2004). 'Old-Stream' Psychology Will
Disappear With the Dinosaurs! Forum Qualitative
Sozialforschung / Forum: Qualitative Social Research, Volume 5,
No. 3, Art. 27 (online journal).
Gergen, K.
(2001). Psychological science in a postmodern context. American
Psychologist, 56, 803-813.
Giddens, A. (1987). Social theory and modern
sociology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Hammersley, M. (2003). Conversation analysis and
discourse: Methods or paradigms? Discourse & Society, 14, 751-781.
Holland, D., Lachicotte, W., Skinner,
D., & Cain, C. (1998). Identity and agency in cultural worlds.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Oyserman,
D., & Markus, H. (1998). Self as social representation. In U. Flick (Ed.), The
psychology of the social (pp. 107-125). New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Ratner, C. (2007). Cultural psychology and qualitative
methodology: Scientific and political considerations. Culture and
Psychology, 13,
Ratner, C. (2006). Cultural psychology: A perspective
on psychological functioning and social reform. Erlbaum.
Ratner, C. (2002).Cultural psychology: Theory and
method. New York: Plenum.
Stanley, L., & Wise, S. (1983).
Breaking out: Feminist consciousness and feminist research. London: Routledge.
Valsiner, J. (1998). The guided mind:
A sociogenetic approach to personality. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.